Thursday, December 17, 2009

Dogville

I just saw Lars von Trier's Dogville over the course of two nights and was struck by the sheer originality of the production and the devastating indictment of American society.  More on this later.

Friday, December 11, 2009

The Baader-Meinhof Complex


Tuesday, December 8, 2009

Napoleon's March

Charles Joseph Minard's figurative chart of Napoleon's Russian campaign.  Edward Tufte describes it as "probably the best statistical graph ever drawn." (click image for larger view)

Wednesday, November 25, 2009

A Proper "Alien" Resurrection

This is a wonderful analysis of the production design involved in Ridley Scott's original Alien, the best of the series.  http://www.theauteurs.com/notebook/posts/831



Sunday, November 22, 2009

Werner Herzog is a Badass Part 2

Only Herzog could diss Abel Ferrara by remaking Bad Lieutenant without seeing the original and get away with it.


Photo from theauteurs.com

Friday, November 20, 2009

The Complete Guide to the Future


The Complete Guide to the Future from Everything Is Terrible on Vimeo.
www.everythingisterrible.com

Sunday, November 15, 2009

Lars Von Trier's "Antichrist"

I just saw Antichrist the other day after reading about it for several months.  These are my early reactions:

John Waters once called Gaspar Noe's Irreversible "The worst date movie in the history of cinema, if this is the first date, you will never get laid."  Due to its brutally violent and sexually explicit content,  Antichrist should merit similar consideration, and I think most people who have seen it will agree.  While we can agree what Antichrist isn't, it will be tough to find common ground on what it is.  Here are my thoughts:



Synopsis:

The plot of Antichrist revolves around a psychologist/therapist and his wife ("He" and "She") played by Willem Dafoe and Charlotte Gainsbourg, respectively.  Following the accidental death of their toddler son, who falls out of a window while the two are making love, She descends into a brutal spiral of guilt and depression.  Feeling that her current therapy is doing little to no good, He decides to treat his wife on his own and toss out her medication.  He decides that She needs to confront her fears directly through "exposure" therapy and after She reveals the source of her fears to be "Eden," their cabin in the woods, they embark on their journey.  Needless to say, things do not work out well for the two of them.  This is, after all, a Lars Von Trier film and he is not the type of director to dole out happy endings in his work.  After a series of bizarre natural incidents and moments of shocking discovery, the film reaches a brutally violent conclusion and Von Trier's camera captures every act in graphic detail.  If you have read anything about this film, you probably know what I am referring to, so there's no need for me to recount them here.  And, I would hate so spoil it for anyone who hasn't seen the film yet.

Cinematography:





Antichrist was filmed digitally with RED One cameras and makes use of several computer effects to create an extraordinary tone for the film, reminiscent of Andrei Tarkovsky's Stalker or The Mirror and some scenes have the exact color palette as those two works.



One of the more effective uses of digital manipulation was the way in which the edges of the frame seemed to warp and distort, as if it were caused by the wind.  It also gave the illusion that the woods were somehow breathing, which is very disconcerting.  The black and white sequences, "Prologue" and "Epilogue," are simply beautiful; making use of slow motion and a haunting score by Handel to set the tone.  These sequences are masterfully executed.



But What Does it Mean?

Much of Antichrist's coverage in the press has focused on the theme of misogyny, accusing Lars Von Trier of having a neanderthal view toward women.  Others believe that the director is simply having fun with the audience by subjecting them to extreme imagery without offering a redeeming message.  A superficial viewing of his latest film would seem to bear this out, but that is neither a perceptive nor even a very interesting take on the film.  I believe what we see on the screen is a different message altogether.  Von Trier himself was battling a severe bout of depression while making this film and I believe we see much of his own struggle translated to the screen.  Willem Dafoe's character represents scientific rationality, or the triumph of man over nature.  He is calm and detached where his wife is hysterical and increasingly irrational.  He, this psychologist and man of science, is so enamored of his own gifts, that he commits the ultimate act of hubris and takes on his own wife as a patient, with disastrous consequences.  Here Von Trier successfully inverts the horror movie genre and by the final act we see the cool, calm, and collected male victimized and imprisoned by the hysterical, irrational woman as well as by nature itself.  Gainsbourg's character, by contrast, is in touch with her emotions and rightly terrified by the power of the natural world, recognizing that His conceptions and beliefs are inadequate for dealing with her own personal demons.  For His arrogance in believing he can control Her inner feelings, he will pay an enormous physical and psychological price.



Returning to the charges of misogyny, I believe Von Trier made the conscious choice to provoke exactly this reaction.  By this I mean that he is attacking the contemporary assumption held by many that women are the victims of history, which is undoubtedly true in the majority of cases.  But is it true of all women?  Gainsbourg's character wrote her graduate thesis on "gynocide," or the burning of "witches" in the seventeenth century.  It is implied that through her research she discovers that some of these women were quite possibly "evil" or deserving of their punishment and worse, that she may be one of them herself, which is borne out by subsequent revelations and events in the film.  The idea that some women are capable of evil deeds should be nothing new but unfortunately this is grounds for charges of misogyny by some critics.  Relegating women to the status of universal victimhood is, I think, a very sexist attitude that deserves a counterargument.  I'm inclined to agree with those critics who view this film as a slyly feminist work, but even more so as a reaction against the arrogance of modern medicine and technology and the received wisdom of "universal" liberal values.  As the fox says: "chaos reigns."



Should it be Seen?

Yes, but only if you have an open mind and are not easily disturbed by violent imagery.  Even fans of traditional horror movies or of the "torture porn" genre might be disappointed, despite the extreme nature of the film, because it is deeper than that.  Antichrist is a film that needs to find its own audience, and I have a feeling Lars Von Trier would want nothing less.  Also, the brave performances by Dafoe and Gainsbourg are nothing short of astounding and deserve the highest praise.  Gainsbourg's Best Actress award at Cannes was well-deserved.  Yes, the film should be seen, but it demands more than a passive viewer seeking "thrills and chills" or "entertainment."  You must be prepared to think about Antichrist, because it will stay with you long after you leave the theater.


ANTICHRIST - OFFICIAL US TRAILER from IFC Films on Vimeo.


Screenshots are from (of all places) http://www.celebritywonder.com They have been saved and uploaded separately, rather than be directly linked, due to the nature of that site (meaning I don't want them to be replaced by ads).

Friday, November 13, 2009

Alien 3: Unrequited Vision

Here is a link to a site describing Vincent Ward's concept for Alien3.  Ward had the revolutionary notion of setting the second Alien sequel on a medieval-style monastery satellite made of wood with windmills, wheat fields, and a glassworks, which would have made for some amazing production design.  The plot revolves around the alien creature wreaking havoc among the community of monks who live there who believe it to be a demon of some kind.  The script can be found here.

Tuesday, November 3, 2009

Wim Wenders: An Attempted Description of an Indescribable Film

Wenders' treatment for Wings of Desire, courtesy of Criterion.

Sunday, November 1, 2009

Final Scene from Tarkovsky's "Stalker."

Saturday, October 31, 2009

Music to be Murdered by

Friday, October 23, 2009

Werner Herzog is a Badass


Thursday, October 22, 2009

US Trailer for Antichrist

ANTICHRIST - OFFICIAL US TRAILER from IFC Films on Vimeo.

Tuesday, October 20, 2009

Orson Whales


Orson Whales from Alex Itin on Vimeo.

A mash up of Orson Welles reading Moby Dick drawn in the pages of Moby Dick with Led Zep and John Bonham playing Moby Dick... with some Champagne thrown in for good measure.
http://www.futureofthebook.org/itinplace/

If Charlie Parker Was a Gunslinger,There'd Be a Whole Lot of Dead Copycats: The Art of Jazz #104

If Charlie Parker Was a Gunslinger,There'd Be a Whole Lot of Dead Copycats: The Art of Jazz #104


Fully Flared: Intro

From Spike Jonze, one of the most original directors in film, with an amazing take on the skate video medium:

Fully Flared Intro from K05T0N on Vimeo.

If Charlie Parker Was a Gunslinger,There'd Be a Whole Lot of Dead Copycats: The Art of Cinema #417

If Charlie Parker Was a Gunslinger,There'd Be a Whole Lot of Dead Copycats: The Art of Cinema #417

Awesome Kinski Poster

Friday, October 16, 2009

My Version of the "Antichrist" Poster

Picture is from Hieronymus Bosch's Hell triptych.

"Antichrist" Poster from Australia

Beautiful, striking, and deeply disturbing.  I'm really looking forward to this film, even though I'll probably regret it.

Tuesday, October 13, 2009

Quotation

"the history that showed things as they really were is the strongest narcotic of our century"
Walter Benjamin

Saturday, October 10, 2009

Kubrick's "Napoleon": The Greatest Movie Never Made

I want this:

Taschen Books

Only $700.00


Monday, October 5, 2009

The Nature of Battle

The Nature of Battle from Nat Dart on Vimeo.

In a ruined world, where mankind has brought destruction upon themselves, a new hope arrives in the form of a seed.



Video: Nat Dart

Music: Matt Kaip

Saturday, September 26, 2009

The Red Detachment of Women

Poster for the 1961 film by Xie Jin.  From The Auteurs.

Friday, September 25, 2009

Characters and Caricatures

By William Hogarth

Distribution of Wealth in 1870

From the Library of Congress

Wednesday, September 23, 2009

Big Trouble in Little China

Taken from dvdbeaver.com


Suspiria



Algiers Casbah

Tuesday, September 15, 2009

Incredible effect; this video looks like stop-motion.


Toy Soldiers from Alta Media Productions on Vimeo.
Photography: Albrecht Gerlach www.albrechtgerlach.com

Production: Tatiana Pereira @ Alta Media Productions

Camera Assistant: Tom Chabbat

Sound: Camille Michel www.unterdecke.com

5DmkII for rent in Paris: www.photocinerent.fr

Cartography in History


Map showing the distribution of woodland in 1873.  From the Library of Congress.Click the image for a better view.

Myths, Metaphors, and Markets: A Reappraisal of Adam Smith’s “Invisible Hand”

It is not from the benevolence of the butcher, the brewer, or the baker that we expect our dinner, but from their regard to their own interest. We address ourselves, not to their humanity but to their self-love, and never talk to them of our own necessities but of their advantages.  –Adam Smith, The Wealth of Nations
            Adam Smith held the Chair of Moral Philosophy at Glasgow University from 1752 to 1763.  While there, he lectured on human nature, the development of societies’ systems of ethics, legal systems, and their relations to the economy.  He also wrote and published The Theory of Moral Sentiments, a work that explored the nature and motive of morality, and would inform all of his subsequent work, including An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations, his most famous work and a foundational text of classical economics.  Neoclassical economists cite Adam Smith as the primary intellectual force behind free market economic policies and laissez-faire capitalism.  Instrumental to this view of Smith is the idea of the “invisible hand” of the marketplace as a regulatory force for overall social good, premised upon self-interested individuals making rational choices, epitomized by the “butcher-baker-brewer” passage above.  Adam Smith was, however, a much more complex thinker than that.  As Amartya Sen argues, “the fact that Smith noted that mutually advantageous trades are very common does not indicate at all that he thought self-love alone, or indeed prudence broadly construed, could be adequate for a good society.  Indeed, he maintained precisely the opposite” (Sen 1987, p.23).  How can we account for this profound difference in interpretation?  This paper will trace the arc of Adam Smith’s intellectual contributions to philosophy and political economy, paying special attention to his use of the “invisible hand” metaphor.  It will also discuss the variations of the “invisible hand” metaphor throughout Smith’s work in order to flesh out what he meant, and in what context.  Finally, the paper will argue that there is more in Adam Smith’s moral philosophy to support “heterodox” economic theories than those of the neoclassical mainstream, which has appropriated his work as its theoretical framework.
            The three main essences of neoclassical theory, as described by George DeMartino, are the consumption proposition, the production proposition, and the scarcity proposition.  By “consumption,” neoclassical economists assume that “individuals are endowed with the ability to choose rationally from among the sets of opportunities they confront.”  This will ensure that individuals make rational, self interested decisions based on what will increate their pleasure, or utility.  Furthermore, a system of preference ordering drives individuals and guides their market transactions, regardless of moral or ethical concerns.  “Production” means that “humans are endowed with the ability to transform elements of nature (through work or labor) so as to produce goods that meet human needs, and they do so rationally.”  This implies a preference for efficiency and higher yields in producing these goods.  Finally, the scarcity proposition implies that “all output (in the form of goods and services) requires inputs from nature, and since nature’s bounty is finite, output must also be finite.”  This third proposition highlights the importance of rational choice in measuring opportunity costs when exchanging for goods and services, as well as demonstrating the inherently competitive nature of economics (DeMartino 2000, pp. 38-41).  The origin of this view of human nature is never explored by mainstream neoclassical economists, it is simply accepted as a given.
            Neoclassical economists view their endeavor as highly scientific, on par with the natural sciences in its objectivity.  They construct models based on assumptions of rational choice, self-interest, and scarcity to predict economic outcomes deemed Pareto-optimal, and therefore beneficial to society as a whole.  Normative judgments of individual choices are withheld in favor of viewing any action as an ordered, rational preference.  The free market is reified as the ultimate, disinterested, arbiter of all matters economic and social.  The intellectual foundation of many of these assumptions can be traced back to Adam Smith and his concept of the “invisible hand” of the marketplace. Indeed, it is widely acknowledged by neoclassical economists that Smith provides the theoretical basis for what they do and who they are.  This link is, however, more tenuous than what contemporary economists may think.  A closer examination of Adam Smith, the moral philosopher is in order.  For this, we will turn to Jerry Evensky and William Grampp, two academic economists who have attempted to “rescue” Smith from the neoclassical economists and reveal the complexity of his thought.
            In “Ethics and the Invisible Hand,” Evensky looks at the various ways that Adam Smith used his most famous metaphor.  Contrary to the popular conception of the term, Evensky argues, “In Adam Smith’s moral philosophy, the invisible hand has a much broader responsibility: if individuals are to enjoy the fruits of a classical liberal society, the invisible hand must not only coordinate individuals’ choices, it must shape the individuals into constructive social beings—ethical beings” (Evensky 1993, p. 197).  While the phrase “invisible hand,” appears only three times in all of Adam Smith’s work, Evensky contends that the concept is central and consistent to the entire canon.  The invisible hand makes its first appearance in Smith’s work in his “History of Astronomy,” an essay on Isaac Newton.  Smith references the “invisible hand of Jupiter,” in describing the role of the Deity in designing the universe, a concept shared by both Smith and Newton.  For Smith, Evensky argues, “The Deity is to the universe as the watchmaker is to a watch.  In each case, it is the hand of the designer that arranges the springs and pins and wheels, and sets the system in motion.  But in both cases that hand is invisible to the spectator who observes only the product of the effort . . .” (Evensky 1993, p. 199).  The Deity is not only a designer, but is benevolent in giving Man the conception of self-love and, more importantly, virtue.  It is individual virtue, not interest that makes for a good social outcome in economic transactions.  Smith notes in The Wealth of Nations:
As in any other beautiful and noble machine that was the production of human art, whatever tended to render its movements more smooth and easy, would derive a beauty from this effect, and, on the contrary, whatever tended to obstruct them would displease upon that account: so virtue, which is, as it were, the fine polish to the wheels of society, necessarily pleases; while vice, like the vile rust, which makes them jar and grate upon one another, is as necessarily offensive. (Smith, 1976 p. 316)
In order for the perfect liberal society to flourish, then, virtue must be integral to the daily conduct of Man.  Furthermore, Smith acknowledges human frailty and the virtual impossibility of reaching the perfect liberal society by simply leaving the “beautiful and noble machine” alone.  In his moral philosophy, Smith believes it is the degree to which humans approach their ethical limit that will determine the overall good of society.
            In The Theory of Moral Sentiments, Smith explores the ways in which society evolves in accordance with the ethics and values of each individual.  Social evolution is achieved in stages, corresponding with economic development, from early hunter-gatherer economies to a commercial society.  Evensky argues:
Since each stage requires a progressively more refined system of human values, the movement of a society from stage to stage is simultaneous with the development of that society's value system. For human progress to occur, each generation must refine the values it inherited from the last, and then must pass those enhanced values on to the next generation through the socialization of its children. Smith sees each individual as being shaped by and in turn, given that person's experience, shaping society (Evensky 1993, p. 201).
For Smith, this evolution is guided by the invisible hand toward the ultimate goal of a free and just society.  He was well aware, however, that this perfect society was a largely unattainable goal.  The invisible hand may be able to guide individuals, but individual actors are ultimately responsible for the kind of society they end up with.  Furthermore, nothing is set in stone, and there can be regressions and detours along the path toward society’s evolution to the liberal ideal. 
At the time he wrote The Theory of Moral Sentiments, Smith had not yet been exposed to the full range of mercantilist economic policy and its characteristic emphasis on accumulation of wealth.  His experience in London, just prior to the publication of the first edition of The Wealth of Nations, showed how the dynamic power of factions and commercial interests affected the English government.  This profoundly affected Smith’s optimism regarding the invisible hand.  In his later years, Smith made several additions and corrections to both The Wealth of Nations and The Theory of Moral Sentiments to reflect his increasing pessimism regarding the market’s ability to foster a good society due to the unintended consequences of economic exchange.  The revisions to The Wealth of Nations included a strong criticism of mercantilism, and how it distorted commercial society, which was “the last stage in the sanguine dynamic Smith had envisioned as guided by the invisible hand.”  In revising The Theory of Moral Sentiments, Smith added a chapter entitled “Character of Virtue,” which “appeals to all citizens to put the well-being of the society before that of any particular faction to which they might belong, and he makes a special plea to those who might be statesmen to step forward and construct a moral society by deed and example” (Evensky 1993, p. 202).  When viewing Smith in this light, it is surprising to see how the “invisible hand” metaphor has been taken by neoclassical economists to mean something as narrow as the unintended consequences of free market transactions.
Evensky is confident that Smith’s “invisible hand” represents the influence of a benevolent designer, the Deity.  He sees this as a consistent theme in Smith’s work from his “History of Astronomy” through The Wealth of Nations.  He contends: “Smith believed that the deity had a purpose, that that purpose was embodied in the design, and that by observing the product of that deity’s hand—nature—he could imagine, at least in general contours, the shape of that design and, in turn, its purpose” (Evensky 2005 p. 31). This interpretation, however, is somewhat reductionist, as it assumes a theoretical consistency in Smith that is rare among great intellectuals.  One always has to take account of the evolution of great ideas when confronted with new evidence and greater sophistication.  Evensky himself acknowledges a change in Smith’s attitude toward the invisible hand when he saw mercantilism in action.  It is quite possible that the invisible hand can mean many things to many people, including Smith himself. 
While it is impossible to know exactly what Smith meant by the “invisible hand,” William Grampp subjects the metaphor to careful textual scrutiny as related to Smith’s The Wealth of Nations and also to the variety of ways others have used it.  In “What Did Smith Mean by the Invisible Hand?” Grampp explores the use and misuse of the term by scholars and economists by subjecting their claims to a careful reading of what Smith actually wrote.  He lays out his main argument by stating:
In my interpretation, the invisible hand is more interesting than it is important. It is a part of an argument for free trade that is astute in several places, is shrewd in a few, specious in some, and in its entirety makes one believe Smith adapted his discourse as much to the misconceptions of his readers as to the truths he wanted them to hold. Or, briefly, the argument shows Smith could be the buncombe artist as well as the professor. Another reason the invisible hand is interesting is that it has become a rhetorical device in the polemics over economic policy, used more often than not as a pejorative to dismiss a simple-minded (or any other kind of) belief in the market. Still another reason is that there is little or no support in what Smith wrote that can substantiate the interpretations it has been given, thus offering another example of how the words of a great man can mean different things to his readers and can be made into something that he himself would not recognize (Grampp 2000 p. 442).
Grampp asserts that, throughout Smith’s work, he used the invisible hand metaphor differently in each instance.  The invisible hand of “History of Astronomy” is distinct from that in The Theory of Moral Sentiments that in turn, is distinct from that in The Wealth of Nations.  In his essay, Grampp identifies no less than nine widely held interpretations of the invisible hand and subjects each to a rigorous analysis based on what is actually stated in Smith’s works.  He is not interested in conjecture, or leaps of faith, but rigorous textual analysis.  His methodology is straightforward: “I should like to propose a way to get things straight about Smith or anyone else. It is to begin by distinguishing between (a) what the author actually said, (b) what is implied by what he said, (c) what can reasonably be inferred from it, (d) what we may conjecture he meant, (e) what he conceivably could have meant, and (f ) what it would be convenient to believe he meant.”  For Grampp, too many economists and scholars have ventured into the territory of (d), (e), and (f), which makes the study of the history of economic ideas “a work of the imagination” (Grampp 2000 p. 443).
            The reference to an “invisible hand” in The Wealth of Nations occurs when Smith describes a condition in which an individual actor who intends to benefit himself in a particular way may, in procuring that benefit, produce a different benefit for everyone, including himself.  The relevant example of this is the decision of an individual to engage in domestic trade instead of foreign trade, where capital is more secure and no less profitable.  In this case, it strengthens the defense of the nation by increasing domestic capital, thus becoming a source of military power.  Grampp goes on to show how this brief passage has produced several divergent interpretations of what Smith meant by the “invisible hand,” including:
1)    The force that makes the interest of one the interest of others
2)    The price mechanism
3)    A figure for the idea of unintended consequences
4)    Competition
5)    The mutual advantage in exchange
6)    A joke
7)    An evolutionary process
8)    Providence
9)    The force that restrains the export of capital
Since it is unlikely that Smith could have possibly intended all nine of these interpretations to be true, Grampp subjects each to his methodological model in order to get to the essence of what Smith intended to say.  For the purposes of this essay, it is helpful to examine Grampp’s analysis of most of these interpretations.
            The first implication, where the self-seeking actions of an individual have the effect of benefiting others, corresponds with the assumptions of neoclassical economists about market actions being mutually beneficial among rational actors.  Grampp acknowledges that this is what Smith says, but only to a certain extent.  In the passage about the invisible hand, Smith describes this relation as being true, but only to the extent that wealth is being kept within the country.  Furthermore, there are certain passages in The Wealth of Nations (Smith 1976 pp. 346, 123, 907) where Smith describes the ways that individuals do not always act rationally in their own interest, such as when they overestimate their chances of success, or when the pursuit of pleasure drives them to ruin.  The self-interested actions of individuals can have the effect of mutual gain, but only if certain conditions are met beforehand.
            The second implication is that the invisible hand is the price mechanism, a force that brings markets into equilibrium and harmony without the intervention of government controls.  Although Smith does discuss the price mechanism, it is not in the context of the invisible hand.  Grampp states: “It is self-interest operating in the fortunate circumstance in which a merchant finds that keeping his capital at home is profitable, the consequence of which is to increase the ability of the nation to defend its people (including the merchant).  That is different from what directs markets” (Grampp 2000, p. 446).  Many welfare economists trace the “First Fundamental Theorem of Welfare Economics,” where all firms and individuals are price takers resulting in Pareto optimal competition, back to the invisible hand argument.  Although this is in agreement with certain other arguments Smith made about markets, Grampp finds no connection to the specific discussion of the invisible hand.
            Tied to, yet separate from the second implication, is the argument, held by most Neo-Austrian economists, that the invisible hand is a metaphor for how a beneficial social order results from the unintended consequences of free market transactions.  Smith does not share the unbounded enthusiasm of Friedrich Hayek or Milton Friedman for the unfettered liberty of capital.  In the case of the invisible hand, the unintended consequence is not a beneficial social order, but a lesser benefit, that of defense of the nation.  In addition, Smith’s advocacy of certain market controls throughout his work indicates that he did not intend that the market, by itself, could produce social good.
            Others assert that the invisible hand is competition, a force that compels actors to pursue their interests wisely and use their resources effectively and efficiently in promoting an overall good, or the public interest.  Although Smith stated that competition is good for management and that monopolies are a bad thing, he did not say these things in the context of describing the invisible hand.  For Smith, the invisible hand is not present in all forms of competitive markets or in all self-interested action.  It is only present when conditions induce merchants to keep their capital at home.  Competition, on its own, does not provide for the defense of the nation.  Grampp reinforces this assertion by citing Smith’s statement that “defense . . . is of much more importance than opulence” (Grampp 2000, p. 447).
            Another interpretation of the invisible hand is the notion that it is the process by which individuals gain the knowledge, skills, and habits for efficient economic conduct.  This is a view advocated by evolutionary psychologists and, to an extent, Evensky when describing the socialization and evolution of morals in The Theory of Moral Sentiments.  Grampp does not deny that skills and knowledge are socially acquired or that they evolve, but he argues that Smith never states or implies that the invisible hand is a result of an evolutionary process.
            Grampp then discusses the conception that the invisible hand is a beneficent power beyond the will of Man, be it the prime mover, an omniscient monitor, or the cause of all human behavior.  It is here where Grampp takes issue with Evensky’s conception of the invisible hand.  Grampp is unequivocal in his assertion that the invisible hand of The Wealth of Nations and that of The Theory of Moral Sentiments are two different things.  In The Theory of Moral Sentiments, Smith clearly references the deity in formulating his moral philosophy, arguing that there is a grand design behind human society and human nature.  This, however, is not the case in The Wealth of Nations.  Grampp argues:
To make [the invisible hand] this in the Wealth of Nations calls for a suspension of belief or for ignoring what Jacob Viner called ‘‘a substantial measure of irreconcilable divergence’’ between the two books. In the Wealth of Nations the invisible hand leads to a beneficial outcome, as this interpretation quite correctly states, but it does so only in particular circumstances. To believe this means the invisible hand is a providential force calls for assuming, first, that providence has made men self-interested (endowed perhaps with the propensity to truck and barter) and, second, that self-interested behavior is always beneficial (Grampp 2000, p. 449).
Whereas Evensky argues for consistency throughout Smith’s writings, Grampp allows for the evolution of Smith’s thought throughout his intellectual career.  He considers The Theory of Moral Sentiments to be an inferior work to The Wealth of Nations in many areas, but especially in the articulation of economic matters.  He argues that Smith’s use of the invisible hand metaphor is completely different in “History of Astronomy,” The Theory of Moral Sentiments, and The Wealth of Nations and does not begrudge Smith the repeated use of an extremely pithy phrase.  Grampp believes: “Until it is demonstrated, the three invisible hands will continue to be, in the mind of at least one reader, three distinct ideas, each of them denoted by the same words” (Grampp 2000, p. 464).
            What can we infer from this analysis that has relevance to the normative issues surrounding global neoliberal policies?  One might be inclined to believe that Evensky and Grampp are merely quibbling about semantics at the expense of Smith’s overall contribution to the canon of economic thought.  There is merit, however, in a close examination of Smith’s work as a useful critique of neoclassical assumptions about economic behavior.  As demonstrated by Grampp, a superficial understanding of The Wealth of Nations has given rise to the dominant understanding of the free market economy by neoclassical economists, who seek to remove all barriers to the export of capital, motivated by the idea that the invisible hand of the marketplace will bring about an equilibrium between supply and demand, or Pareto optimality.  That this process is understood as scientific or devoid of ethical connotations reveals a disturbing normative contradiction underlying neoclassical economics.
            Adam Smith’s lessons from The Theory of Moral Sentiments and The Wealth of Nations continue to have relevance to today’s economic policies of globalization.  In fact, there are several striking examples of congruence between his views and those of heterodox economists and other critics of neoliberalism.  Take, for example, Smith’s critique of mercantilism, which had shaken him so much as to revise his views in The Wealth of Nations.  Evensky shows how Smith lost faith in the invisible hand’s ability to produce just outcomes in economic affairs, indeed it led to a major reformulation of his ethical outlook.  If the invisible hand could not guide society toward the ethical ideal, it would fall to political leaders to construct a moral society by deed and example.  As Grampp notes, some of these deeds come in the form of the 35-40 types of government intervention that Smith advocates, such as the taxing of spirits, the regulation of certain markets, the redistribution of income through taxation, and currency regulation, to name just a few.  Contrast this more subtle view of Smithian economics than that offered by Milton Friedman in Capitalism and Freedom, where he argues for separation between the political and economic spheres:
Viewed as a means to the end of political freedom, economic arrangements are important because of their effect on the concentration or dispersion of power. The kind of economic organization that provides economic freedom directly, namely, competitive capitalism, also promotes political freedom because it separates economic power from political power and in this way enables the one to offset the other (Friedman 1962).
In this sense, Smith’s advocacy of government intervention in the economy undermines the dominant neoclassical view of the free market as ultimate arbiter of social welfare and reflects more of a concern for social justice in the face of dominant factions that undermine the welfare of a nation’s citizens. 
            Heterodox economists, such as George DeMartino, who advocate careful regulation of the global economy through tariff and labor mobility regimes can find some of the elements of a commitment to justice in Smith’s work, especially in his later period, as he reassessed the ability of the market to produce just economic outcomes (DeMartino 2000 pp. 218-236).  Other critics, such as J.K. Gibson-Graham, who advocate economic alternatives to global neoliberalism in the form of highly localized economies can also look to Smith’s explicit discussion of the invisible hand in The Wealth of Nations, which argues in favor of limiting the mobility of capital under the correct circumstances (Gibson-Graham 2003).
            When discussing the legacy of a revered intellectual figure such as Adam Smith, one must be careful when describing the full depth of his contribution to the social sciences.  It is in the interest of accuracy that writers such as Jerry Evensky and William Grampp seek to present their versions of Smith’s philosophy, yet they reach differing conclusions.  History, and especially intellectual history is far from being a hard science.  It is laden with prejudices, context-dependent, and subjective.  In other words, it is the opposite of what neoclassical economists claim that they do.  Through the course of this essay, the legacy of Adam Smith has been shown to be mutable and often contradictory.  I argue that this is not necessarily a bad thing; people evolve in their views and their outlooks throughout the course of their lives and this is natural.  Intellectual historians need to recognize this about their subjects: that they are enigmatic.  It is a fool’s errand to try to find concrete or universal similarities throughout any great author or artist’s canon, because it assumes a level of intellectual stagnation.  In Grampp’s conclusion to his article, he compares the work of Adam Smith to Elgar’s Enigma variations in classical music, concluding: “Smith believed property rights should be protected, except when they should not be, and that is another enigma” (Grampp 2000, p. 464).  Looking at the intellectual contributions of “classical” economists in this way de-essentializes them, which may in turn complicate our understanding of them, but it opens the way for substantive criticism of the so-called hard science of neoclassical economics.  This is not a destructive endeavor, but one that can act as an agent for constructive change.
References
DeMartino, George. Global Economy, Global Justice: Theoretical Objections and Policy Alternatives to Neoliberalism, New York: Routledge, 2000.
Evensky, Jerry. Adam Smith’s Moral Philosophy: A Historical and Contemporary Perspective on Markets, Law, Ethics, and Culture, New York: Cambridge University Press, 2005.
Evensky, Jerry. “Ethics and the Invisible Hand,” Journal of Economic Perspectives, Vol. 7, No. 2, 1993.
Evensky, Jerry. “Adam Smith’s Theory of Moral Sentiments: On Morals and Why They Matter to a Liberal Society of Free People and Free Markets,” Journal of Economic Perspectives, Vol. 19, No. 3, 2005.
Friedman, Milton. Capitalism and Freedom, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1962.
Gibson-Graham, J.K. “An Ethics of the Local,” Rethinking Marxism, Vol. 15, No.1, 2003.
Grampp, William D. “What Did Smith Mean by The Invisible Hand?” Journal of Political Economy, Vol. 108, No. 3, 2000.
Sen, Amartya. On Ethics and Economics, Malden, MA: Blackwell, 1987.

Wednesday, September 2, 2009


SIEGFRIED from Martin Inda on Vimeo.

An amazing production of Wagner's Siegfried at Ciudad de las Ciencias y Artes, Valencia-Spain, June 2008.